(** * ProofObjects: The Curry-Howard Correspondence *) Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing,-deprecated-hint-without-locality". From LF Require Export IndProp. (** "Algorithms are the computational content of proofs." (Robert Harper) *) (** Programming and proving in Coq are two sides of the same coin. Proofs manipulate evidence, much as programs manipulate data. *) (** Question: If evidence is data, what are propositions themselves? Answer: They are types! *) (** Look again at the formal definition of the [ev] property. *) Inductive ev : nat -> Prop := | ev_0 : ev 0 | ev_SS (n : nat) (H : ev n) : ev (S (S n)). (** Suppose we introduce an alternative pronunciation of "[:]". Instead of "has type," we can say "is a proof of." For example, the second line in the definition of [ev] declares that [ev_0 : ev 0]. Instead of "[ev_0] has type [ev 0]," we can say that "[ev_0] is a proof of [ev 0]." *) (** This pun between types and propositions -- between [:] as "has type" and [:] as "is a proof of" or "is evidence for" -- is called the _Curry-Howard correspondence_. It proposes a deep connection between the world of logic and the world of computation: propositions ~ types proofs ~ data values See [Wadler 2015] (in Bib.v) for a brief history and up-to-date exposition. *) (** Many useful insights follow from this connection. To begin with, it gives us a natural interpretation of the type of the [ev_SS] constructor: *) Check ev_SS : forall n, ev n -> ev (S (S n)). (** This can be read "[ev_SS] is a constructor that takes two arguments -- a number [n] and evidence for the proposition [ev n] -- and yields evidence for the proposition [ev (S (S n))]." *) (** Now let's look again at a previous proof involving [ev]. *) Theorem ev_4 : ev 4. Proof. apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply ev_0. Qed. (** As with ordinary data values and functions, we can use the [Print] command to see the _proof object_ that results from this proof script. *) Print ev_4. (* ===> ev_4 = ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0) : ev 4 *) (** Indeed, we can also write down this proof object directly, without the need for a separate proof script: *) Check (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)) : ev 4. (** Similarly, as we've seen, we can directly apply theorems to arguments in proof scripts: *) Theorem ev_4': ev 4. Proof. apply (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)). Qed. (* ################################################################# *) (** * Proof Scripts *) (** When we write a proof using tactics, what we are doing is instructing Coq to build a proof object under the hood. We can see this using [Show Proof]: *) Theorem ev_4'' : ev 4. Proof. Show Proof. apply ev_SS. Show Proof. apply ev_SS. Show Proof. apply ev_0. Show Proof. Qed. (** Tactic proofs are convenient, but they are not essential in Coq: in principle, we can always just construct the required evidence by hand. Then we can use [Definition] (rather than [Theorem]) to introduce a global name for this evidence. *) Definition ev_4''' : ev 4 := ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0). (* ################################################################# *) (** * Quantifiers, Implications, Functions *) (** In Coq's computational universe (where data structures and programs live), there are two sorts of values that have arrows in their types: _constructors_ introduced by [Inductive]ly defined data types, and _functions_. Similarly, in Coq's logical universe (where we carry out proofs), there are two ways of giving evidence for an implication: constructors introduced by [Inductive]ly defined propositions, and... functions! *) (** For example, consider this statement: *) Theorem ev_plus4 : forall n, ev n -> ev (4 + n). Proof. intros n H. simpl. apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply H. Qed. (** What is the proof object corresponding to [ev_plus4]? We're looking for an expression whose _type_ is [forall n, ev n -> ev (4 + n)] -- that is, a _function_ that takes two arguments (one number and a piece of evidence) and returns a piece of evidence! Here it is: *) Definition ev_plus4' : forall n, ev n -> ev (4 + n) := fun (n : nat) => fun (H : ev n) => ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H). (** Or equivalently: *) Definition ev_plus4'' (n : nat) (H : ev n) : ev (4 + n) := ev_SS (S (S n)) (ev_SS n H). Check ev_plus4'' : forall n : nat, ev n -> ev (4 + n). (** When we view the proposition being proved by [ev_plus4] as a function type, one interesting point becomes apparent: The second argument's type, [ev n], mentions the _value_ of the first argument, [n]. While such _dependent types_ are not found in most mainstream programming languages, they can be quite useful in programming too, as the flurry of activity in the functional programming community over the past couple of decades demonstrates. *) (** Notice that both implication ([->]) and quantification ([forall]) correspond to functions on evidence. In fact, they are really the same thing: [->] is just a shorthand for a degenerate use of [forall] where there is no dependency, i.e., no need to give a name to the type on the left-hand side of the arrow: forall (x:nat), nat = forall (_:nat), nat = nat -> nat *) (* QUIZ Recall the definition of [ev]: Inductive ev : nat -> Prop := | ev_0 : ev 0 | ev_SS : forall n, ev n -> ev (S (S n)). What is the type of this expression? fun (n : nat) => fun (H : ev n) => ev_SS (2 + n) (ev_SS n H) (1) [forall n, ev n] (2) [forall n, ev (2 + n)] (3) [forall n, ev n -> ev n] (4) [forall n, ev n -> ev (2 + n)] (5) [forall n, ev n -> ev (4 + n)] (6) Not typeable *) (* ################################################################# *) (** * Programming with Tactics *) (** If we can build proofs by giving explicit terms rather than executing tactic scripts, you may be wondering whether we can build _programs_ using tactics rather than by writing down explicit terms. Naturally, the answer is yes! *) Definition add1 : nat -> nat. intro n. Show Proof. apply S. Show Proof. apply n. Defined. Print add1. (* ==> add1 = fun n : nat => S n : nat -> nat *) Compute add1 2. (* ==> 3 : nat *) (* ################################################################# *) (** * Logical Connectives as Inductive Types *) (** Inductive definitions are powerful enough to express most of the connectives we have seen so far. Indeed, only universal quantification (with implication as a special case) is built into Coq; all the others are defined inductively. Let's see how. *) Module Props. (* ================================================================= *) (** ** Conjunction *) (** To prove that [P /\ Q] holds, we must present evidence for both [P] and [Q]. Thus, it makes sense to define a proof object for [P /\ Q] to consist of a pair of two proofs: one for [P] and another one for [Q]. This leads to the following definition. *) Module And. Inductive and (P Q : Prop) : Prop := | conj : P -> Q -> and P Q. Arguments conj [P] [Q]. Notation "P /\ Q" := (and P Q) : type_scope. (** Notice the similarity with the definition of the [prod] type, given in chapter [Poly]; the only difference is that [prod] takes [Type] arguments, whereas [and] takes [Prop] arguments. *) Print prod. (* ===> Inductive prod (X Y : Type) : Type := | pair : X -> Y -> X * Y. *) (** This similarity should clarify why [destruct] and [intros] patterns can be used on a conjunctive hypothesis. Case analysis allows us to consider all possible ways in which [P /\ Q] was proved -- here just one (the [conj] constructor). *) Theorem proj1' : forall P Q, P /\ Q -> P. Proof. intros P Q HPQ. destruct HPQ as [HP HQ]. apply HP. Show Proof. Qed. (** Similarly, the [split] tactic actually works for any inductively defined proposition with exactly one constructor. In particular, it works for [and]: *) Lemma and_comm : forall P Q : Prop, P /\ Q <-> Q /\ P. Proof. intros P Q. split. - intros [HP HQ]. split. + apply HQ. + apply HP. - intros [HQ HP]. split. + apply HP. + apply HQ. Qed. End And. (** This shows why the inductive definition of [and] can be manipulated by tactics as we've been doing. We can also use it to build proofs directly, using pattern-matching. For instance: *) Definition and_comm'_aux P Q (H : P /\ Q) : Q /\ P := match H with | conj HP HQ => conj HQ HP end. Definition and_comm' P Q : P /\ Q <-> Q /\ P := conj (and_comm'_aux P Q) (and_comm'_aux Q P). (* QUIZ What is the type of this expression? fun P Q R (H1: and P Q) (H2: and Q R) => match (H1,H2) with | (conj HP _, conj _ HR) => conj HP HR end. (1) [forall P Q R, P /\ Q -> Q /\ R -> P /\ R] (2) [forall P Q R, Q /\ P -> R /\ Q -> P /\ R] (3) [forall P Q R, P /\ R] (4) [forall P Q R, P \/ Q -> Q \/ R -> P \/ R] (5) Not typeable *) (* ================================================================= *) (** ** Disjunction *) (** The inductive definition of disjunction uses two constructors, one for each side of the disjunct: *) Module Or. Inductive or (P Q : Prop) : Prop := | or_introl : P -> or P Q | or_intror : Q -> or P Q. Arguments or_introl [P] [Q]. Arguments or_intror [P] [Q]. Notation "P \/ Q" := (or P Q) : type_scope. (** This declaration explains the behavior of the [destruct] tactic on a disjunctive hypothesis, since the generated subgoals match the shape of the [or_introl] and [or_intror] constructors. *) (** Once again, we can also directly write proof objects for theorems involving [or], without resorting to tactics. *) Definition inj_l : forall (P Q : Prop), P -> P \/ Q := fun P Q HP => or_introl HP. Theorem inj_l' : forall (P Q : Prop), P -> P \/ Q. Proof. intros P Q HP. left. apply HP. Qed. Definition or_elim : forall (P Q R : Prop), (P \/ Q) -> (P -> R) -> (Q -> R) -> R := fun P Q R HPQ HPR HQR => match HPQ with | or_introl HP => HPR HP | or_intror HQ => HQR HQ end. Theorem or_elim' : forall (P Q R : Prop), (P \/ Q) -> (P -> R) -> (Q -> R) -> R. Proof. intros P Q R HPQ HPR HQR. destruct HPQ as [HP | HQ]. - apply HPR. apply HP. - apply HQR. apply HQ. Qed. End Or. (* QUIZ What is the type of this expression? fun P Q H => match H with | or_introl HP => @or_intror Q P HP | or_intror HQ => @or_introl Q P HQ end. (1) [forall P Q H, Q \/ P \/ H] (2) [forall P Q, P \/ Q -> P \/ Q] (3) [forall P Q H, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P -> H] (4) [forall P Q, P \/ Q -> Q \/ P] (5) Not typeable *) (* ================================================================= *) (** ** Existential Quantification *) (** To give evidence for an existential quantifier, we package a witness [x] together with a proof that [x] satisfies the property [P]: *) Module Ex. Inductive ex {A : Type} (P : A -> Prop) : Prop := | ex_intro : forall x : A, P x -> ex P. Notation "'exists' x , p" := (ex (fun x => p)) (at level 200, right associativity) : type_scope. End Ex. (** The more familiar form [exists x, P x] desugars to an expression involving [ex]: *) Check ex (fun n => ev n) : Prop. (** Here's how to define an explicit proof object involving [ex]: *) Definition some_nat_is_even : exists n, ev n := ex_intro ev 4 (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)). (* QUIZ Which of the following propositions is proved by providing an explicit witness [w] using [exist w]? (1) [forall x: nat, (exists n, x = S n) -> (x<>0)] (2) [forall x: nat, (x<>0) -> (exists n, x = S n)] (3) [forall x: nat, (x=0) -> ~(exists n, x = S n)] (4) [forall x: nat, x = 4 -> (x<>0)] (5) none of the above *) (* ================================================================= *) (** ** [True] and [False] *) (** The inductive definition of the [True] proposition is simple: *) Inductive True : Prop := | I : True. (** It has one constructor (so every proof of [True] is the same, so being given a proof of [True] is not informative.) *) (** [False] is equally simple -- indeed, so simple it may look syntactically wrong at first glance! *) Inductive False : Prop := . (** That is, [False] is an inductive type with _no_ constructors -- i.e., no way to build evidence for it. For example, there is no way to complete the following definition such that it succeeds. *) Fail Definition contra : False := 0 = 1. (** But it is possible to destruct [False] by pattern matching. There can be no patterns that match it, since it has no constructors. So the pattern match also is so simple it may look syntactically wrong at first glance. *) Definition false_implies_zero_eq_one : False -> 0 = 1 := fun contra => match contra with end. (** Since there are no branches to evaluate, the [match] expression can be considered to have any type we want, including [0 = 1]. Fortunately, it's impossible to ever cause the [match] to be evaluated, because we can never construct a value of type [False] to pass to the function. *) End Props. (* ################################################################# *) (** * Equality *) (** Even Coq's equality relation is not built in. We can define it ourselves: *) Module EqualityPlayground. Inductive eq {X:Type} : X -> X -> Prop := | eq_refl : forall x, eq x x. Notation "x == y" := (eq x y) (at level 70, no associativity) : type_scope. (** Coq terms are "the same" if they are _convertible_ according to a simple set of computation rules: evaluation of function applications, inlining of definitions, and simplification of [match]es. *) Lemma four: 2 + 2 == 1 + 3. Proof. apply eq_refl. Qed. (** [reflexivity] is essentially just [apply eq_refl]. *) Definition four' : 2 + 2 == 1 + 3 := eq_refl 4. Definition singleton : forall (X:Type) (x:X), []++[x] == x::[] := fun (X:Type) (x:X) => eq_refl [x]. Definition eq_add : forall (n1 n2 : nat), n1 == n2 -> (S n1) == (S n2) := fun n1 n2 Heq => match Heq with | eq_refl n => eq_refl (S n) end. (* QUIZ Which of the following is a correct proof object for the proposition exists x, x + 3 == 4 ? (1) [eq_refl 4] (2) [ex_intro (fun z => (z + 3 == 4)) 1 eq_refl] (3) [ex_intro (z + 3 == 4) 1 (eq_refl 4)] (4) [ex_intro (fun z => (z + 3 == 4)) 1 (eq_refl 4)] (5) [ex_intro (fun z => (z + 3 == 4)) 1 (eq_refl 1)] (6) none of the above *) End EqualityPlayground. (* ################################################################# *) (** * Coq's Trusted Computing Base *) (** The Coq typechecker is what actually checks our proofs. We have to trust it, but it's relatively small and straightforward. *) (** For example, it rejects this broken proof: *) Fail Definition or_bogus : forall P Q, P \/ Q -> P := fun (P Q : Prop) (A : P \/ Q) => match A with | or_introl H => H end. (** And these: *) Fail Fixpoint infinite_loop {X : Type} (n : nat) {struct n} : X := infinite_loop n. Fail Definition falso : False := infinite_loop 0. (** Complex tactics can (in principle and occasionally in practice) produce invalid proof objects. [Qed] runs the type checker to detect such situations. *)