LogicLogic in Coq
We have seen...
In this chapter we will introduce several more flavors of both
propositions and proofs.
Like everything in Coq, propositions are typed:
- propositions: factual claims
- equality propositions (e1 = e2)
- implications (P → Q)
- quantified propositions (∀ x, P)
- proofs: ways of presenting evidence for the truth of a proposition
Check 3 = 3 : Prop.
Check ∀ n m : nat, n + m = m + n : Prop.
Note that all syntactically well-formed propositions have type Prop in Coq, regardless of whether they are true.
Check 2 = 2 : Prop.
Check 3 = 2 : Prop.
Check ∀ n : nat, n = 2 : Prop.
So far, we've seen one primary place that propositions can appear: in Theorem (and Lemma and Example) declarations.
Theorem plus_2_2_is_4 :
2 + 2 = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Definition plus_claim : Prop := 2 + 2 = 4.
Check plus_claim : Prop.
Theorem plus_claim_is_true :
plus_claim.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
We can also write parameterized propositions -- that is, functions that take arguments of some type and return a proposition.
Definition is_three (n : nat) : Prop :=
n = 3.
Check is_three : nat → Prop.
In Coq, functions that return propositions are said to define properties of their arguments.
Definition injective {A B} (f : A → B) :=
∀ x y : A, f x = f y → x = y.
Lemma succ_inj : injective S.
Proof.
intros n m H. injection H as H1. apply H1.
Qed.
The equality operator = is also a function that returns a Prop.
Check @eq : ∀ A : Type, A → A → Prop.
What is the type of the following expression?
pred (S O) = O
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) ∀ n:nat, Prop
(4) nat→nat
(5) Not typeable
pred (S O) = O
What is the type of the following expression?
∀ n:nat, pred (S n) = n
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) ∀ n:nat, Prop
(4) nat→nat
(5) Not typeable
∀ n:nat, pred (S n) = n
What is the type of the following expression?
∀ n:nat, S (pred n) = n
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) nat→nat
(4) Not typeable
∀ n:nat, S (pred n) = n
What is the type of the following expression?
∀ n:nat, S (pred n)
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) nat→nat
(4) Not typeable
∀ n:nat, S (pred n)
(* Check (forall n:nat, pred (S n)). *)
(* ===> Error: In environment
n : nat
The term "pred (S n)" has type "nat" which should be Set, Prop or Type. *)
(* ===> Error: In environment
n : nat
The term "pred (S n)" has type "nat" which should be Set, Prop or Type. *)
What is the type of the following expression?
fun n:nat ⇒ S (pred n)
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) nat→nat
(4) Not typeable
fun n:nat ⇒ S (pred n)
What is the type of the following expression?
fun n:nat ⇒ S (pred n) = n
(1) Prop
(2) nat→Prop
(3) nat→nat
(4) Not typeable
fun n:nat ⇒ S (pred n) = n
Which of the following is not a proposition?
(1) 3 + 2 = 4
(2) 3 + 2 = 5
(3) 3 + 2 =? 5
(4) (3+2) =? 4 = false
(5) ∀ n, (3+2) =? n = true → n = 5
(6) All of these are propositions
Fail Definition bad : Prop := 3 + 2 =? 5.
(* The command has indeed failed with message: *)
(* The term "3 + 2 =? 5" has type "bool" while it is expected to have type "Prop". *)
(* The command has indeed failed with message: *)
(* The term "3 + 2 =? 5" has type "bool" while it is expected to have type "Prop". *)
Logical Connectives
Conjunction
Example and_example : 3 + 4 = 7 ∧ 2 × 2 = 4.
To prove a conjunction, use the split tactic. It will generate
two subgoals, one for each part of the statement:
Proof.
split.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 * 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
For any propositions A and B, if we assume that A is true and that B is true, we can conclude that A ∧ B is also true.
Lemma and_intro : ∀ A B : Prop, A → B → A ∧ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA HB. split.
- apply HA.
- apply HB.
Qed.
Since applying a theorem with hypotheses to some goal has the effect of generating as many subgoals as there are hypotheses for that theorem, we can apply and_intro to achieve the same effect as split.
Example and_example' : 3 + 4 = 7 ∧ 2 × 2 = 4.
Proof.
apply and_intro.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 + 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
Example and_exercise :
∀ n m : nat, n + m = 0 → n = 0 ∧ m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
So much for proving conjunctive statements. To go in the other direction -- i.e., to use a conjunctive hypothesis to help prove something else -- we employ the destruct tactic.
Lemma and_example2 :
∀ n m : nat, n = 0 ∧ m = 0 → n + m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
As usual, we can also destruct H right when we introduce it, instead of introducing and then destructing it:
Lemma and_example2' :
∀ n m : nat, n = 0 ∧ m = 0 → n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
You may wonder why we bothered packing the two hypotheses n = 0 and m = 0 into a single conjunction, since we could have also stated the theorem with two separate premises:
Lemma and_example2'' :
∀ n m : nat, n = 0 → m = 0 → n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m Hn Hm.
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
For the present example, both ways work. But in other
situations we may wind up with a conjunctive hypothesis in the
middle of a proof...
Lemma and_example3 :
∀ n m : nat, n + m = 0 → n × m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
By the way, the infix notation ∧ is actually just syntactic sugar for and A B. That is, and is a Coq operator that takes two propositions as arguments and yields a proposition.
Check and : Prop → Prop → Prop.
Disjunction
To use a disjunctive hypothesis in a proof, we proceed by case analysis (which, as with other data types like nat, can be done explicitly with destruct or implicitly with an intros pattern):
Lemma eq_mult_0 :
∀ n m : nat, n = 0 ∨ m = 0 → n × m = 0.
Proof.
(* This pattern implicitly does case analysis on
n = 0 ∨ m = 0 *)
intros n m [Hn | Hm].
- (* Here, n = 0 *)
rewrite Hn. reflexivity.
- (* Here, m = 0 *)
rewrite Hm. rewrite <- mult_n_O.
reflexivity.
Qed.
We can see in this example that, when we perform case
analysis on a disjunction A ∨ B, we must separately satisfy two
proof obligations, each showing that the conclusion holds under a
different assumption -- A in the first subgoal and B in the
second. Note that the case analysis pattern [Hn | Hm] allows
us to name the hypotheses that are generated in the subgoals.
Conversely, to show that a disjunction holds, it suffices to show that one of its sides holds. This is done via two tactics, left and right. As their names imply, the first one requires proving the left side of the disjunction, while the second requires proving its right side. Here is a trivial use...
Lemma or_intro_l : ∀ A B : Prop, A → A ∨ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA.
left.
apply HA.
Qed.
Lemma zero_or_succ :
∀ n : nat, n = 0 ∨ n = S (pred n).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Falsehood and Negation
So far, we have mostly been concerned with proving that certain things are true -- addition is commutative, appending lists is associative, etc. Of course, we may also be interested in negative results, demonstrating that some given proposition is not true. Such statements are expressed with the logical negation operator ¬.To see how negation works, recall the principle of explosion from the Tactics chapter, which asserts that, if we assume a contradiction, then any other proposition can be derived.
Module MyNot.
Definition not (P:Prop) := P → False.
Notation "~ x" := (not x) : type_scope.
Check not : Prop → Prop.
End MyNot.
Since False is a contradictory proposition, the principle of explosion also applies to it. If we get False into the proof context, we can use destruct on it to complete any goal:
Theorem ex_falso_quodlibet : ∀ (P:Prop),
False → P.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Inequality is a frequent enough example of negated statement that there is a special notation for it, x ≠ y:
Notation "x <> y" := (~(x = y)).
Theorem zero_not_one : 0 ≠ 1.
Proof.
unfold not.
intros contra.
discriminate contra.
Qed.
It takes a little practice to get used to working with negation in Coq. Even though you can see perfectly well why a statement involving negation is true, it can be a little tricky at first to make Coq understand it! Here are proofs of a few familiar facts to get you warmed up.
Theorem not_False :
¬False.
Proof.
unfold not. intros H. destruct H. Qed.
Theorem contradiction_implies_anything : ∀ P Q : Prop,
(P ∧ ¬P) → Q.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Theorem double_neg : ∀ P : Prop,
P → ~~P.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
(P ∧ ¬P) → Q.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Theorem double_neg : ∀ P : Prop,
P → ~~P.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Since inequality involves a negation, it also requires a little practice to be able to work with it fluently. Here is one useful trick. If you are trying to prove a goal that is nonsensical (e.g., the goal state is false = true), apply ex_falso_quodlibet to change the goal to False. This makes it easier to use assumptions of the form ¬P that may be available in the context -- in particular, assumptions of the form x≠y.
Theorem not_true_is_false : ∀ b : bool,
b ≠ true → b = false.
Proof.
intros b H.
destruct b eqn:HE.
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet.
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
Since reasoning with ex_falso_quodlibet is quite common, Coq provides a built-in tactic, exfalso, for applying it.
Theorem not_true_is_false' : ∀ b : bool,
b ≠ true → b = false.
Proof.
intros [] H. (* note implicit destruct b here *)
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
exfalso. (* <=== *)
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *) reflexivity.
Qed.
To prove the following proposition, which tactics will we need
besides intros and apply?
∀ X, ∀ a b : X, (a=b) ∧ (a≠b) → False.
(1) destruct, unfold, left and right
(2) destruct and unfold
(3) only destruct
(4) left and/or right
(5) only unfold
(6) none of the above
∀ X, ∀ a b : X, (a=b) ∧ (a≠b) → False.
Lemma quiz1: ∀ X, ∀ a b : X, (a=b) ∧ (a≠b) → False.
Proof.
intros X a b [H0 H1]. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
Qed.
Proof.
intros X a b [H0 H1]. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
Qed.
To prove the following proposition, which tactics will we
need besides intros and apply?
∀ P Q : Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~(P ∨ Q).
(1) destruct, unfold, left and right
(2) destruct and unfold
(3) only destruct
(4) left and/or right
(5) only unfold
(6) none of the above
∀ P Q : Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~(P ∨ Q).
Lemma quiz2 :
∀ P Q : Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~(P ∨ Q).
Proof.
intros P Q H H1. apply H1 in H. apply H.
Qed.
∀ P Q : Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~(P ∨ Q).
Proof.
intros P Q H H1. apply H1 in H. apply H.
Qed.
To prove the following proposition, which tactics will we
need besides intros and apply?
∀ A B: Prop, A → (A ∨ ~~B).
(1) destruct, unfold, left and right
(2) destruct and unfold
(3) only destruct
(4) left and/or right
(5) only unfold
(6) none of the above
∀ A B: Prop, A → (A ∨ ~~B).
Lemma quiz3 :
∀ A B: Prop, A → (A ∨ ~~B).
Proof.
intros P Q H. left. apply H.
Qed.
∀ A B: Prop, A → (A ∨ ~~B).
Proof.
intros P Q H. left. apply H.
Qed.
To prove the following proposition, which tactics will we need
besides intros and apply?
∀ P Q: Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~P ∨ ~~Q.
(1) destruct, unfold, left and right
(2) destruct and unfold
(3) only destruct
(4) left and/or right
(5) only unfold
(6) none of the above
∀ P Q: Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~P ∨ ~~Q.
Lemma quiz4 :
∀ P Q: Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~P ∨ ~~Q.
Proof.
intros P Q [H0 | H0].
- (* left *)
left. intros H1. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
- (* right *)
right. intros H1. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
Qed.
∀ P Q: Prop, P ∨ Q → ~~P ∨ ~~Q.
Proof.
intros P Q [H0 | H0].
- (* left *)
left. intros H1. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
- (* right *)
right. intros H1. apply H1 in H0. apply H0.
Qed.
To prove the following proposition, which tactics will we need
besides intros and apply?
∀ A : Prop, 1=0 → (A ∨ ¬A).
(1) discriminate, unfold, left and right
(2) discriminate and unfold
(3) only discriminate
(4) left and/or right
(5) only unfold
(6) none of the above
∀ A : Prop, 1=0 → (A ∨ ¬A).
Lemma quiz5 :
∀ A : Prop, 1=0 → (A ∨ ¬A).
Proof.
intros P H. discriminate H.
Qed.
∀ A : Prop, 1=0 → (A ∨ ¬A).
Proof.
intros P H. discriminate H.
Qed.
Truth
Lemma True_is_true : True.
Proof. apply I. Qed.
Unlike False, which is used extensively, True is used quite
rarely, since it is trivial (and therefore uninteresting) to prove
as a goal, and it carries no useful information as a hypothesis.
The handy "if and only if" connective, which asserts that two
propositions have the same truth value, is simply the conjunction
of two implications.
Logical Equivalence
Module MyIff.
Definition iff (P Q : Prop) := (P → Q) ∧ (Q → P).
Notation "P <-> Q" := (iff P Q)
(at level 95, no associativity)
: type_scope.
End MyIff.
Theorem iff_sym : ∀ P Q : Prop,
(P ↔ Q) → (Q ↔ P).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Lemma not_true_iff_false : ∀ b,
b ≠ true ↔ b = false.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
(P ↔ Q) → (Q ↔ P).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Lemma not_true_iff_false : ∀ b,
b ≠ true ↔ b = false.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Setoids and Logical Equivalence
From Coq Require Import Setoids.Setoid.
A "setoid" is a set equipped with an equivalence relation,
such as = or ↔.
Example: Using rewrite with ↔.
Lemma mult_0 : ∀ n m, n × m = 0 ↔ n = 0 ∨ m = 0.
Proof.
split.
- apply mult_eq_0.
- apply eq_mult_0.
Qed.
split.
- apply mult_eq_0.
- apply eq_mult_0.
Qed.
Theorem or_assoc :
∀ P Q R : Prop, P ∨ (Q ∨ R) ↔ (P ∨ Q) ∨ R.
Proof.
intros P Q R. split.
- intros [H | [H | H]].
+ left. left. apply H.
+ left. right. apply H.
+ right. apply H.
- intros [[H | H] | H].
+ left. apply H.
+ right. left. apply H.
+ right. right. apply H.
Qed.
intros P Q R. split.
- intros [H | [H | H]].
+ left. left. apply H.
+ left. right. apply H.
+ right. apply H.
- intros [[H | H] | H].
+ left. apply H.
+ right. left. apply H.
+ right. right. apply H.
Qed.
Lemma mult_0_3 :
∀ n m p, n × m × p = 0 ↔ n = 0 ∨ m = 0 ∨ p = 0.
Proof.
intros n m p.
rewrite mult_0. rewrite mult_0. rewrite or_assoc.
reflexivity.
Qed.
Example: using apply with ↔. The apply tactic can also be used with ↔. When given an equivalence as its argument, apply tries to guess which direction of the equivalence will be useful.
Lemma apply_iff_example :
∀ n m : nat, n × m = 0 → n = 0 ∨ m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m H. apply mult_0. apply H.
Qed.
Existential Quantification
Definition even x := ∃ n : nat, x = double n.
Lemma four_is_even : even 4.
Proof.
unfold even. ∃ 2. reflexivity.
Qed.
Conversely, if we have an existential hypothesis ∃ x, P in the context, we can destruct it to obtain a witness x and a hypothesis stating that P holds of x.
Theorem exists_example_2 : ∀ n,
(∃ m, n = 4 + m) →
(∃ o, n = 2 + o).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Programming with Propositions
- If l is the empty list, then x cannot occur in it, so the property "x appears in l" is simply false.
- Otherwise, l has the form x' :: l'. In this case, x occurs in l if either it is equal to x' or it occurs in l'.
Fixpoint In {A : Type} (x : A) (l : list A) : Prop :=
match l with
| [] ⇒ False
| x' :: l' ⇒ x' = x ∨ In x l'
end.
Example In_example_1 : In 4 [1; 2; 3; 4; 5].
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Example In_example_2 :
∀ n, In n [2; 4] →
∃ n', n = 2 × n'.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Theorem In_map :
∀ (A B : Type) (f : A → B) (l : list A) (x : A),
In x l →
In (f x) (map f l).
Proof.
intros A B f l x.
induction l as [|x' l' IHl'].
- (* l = nil, contradiction *)
simpl. intros [].
- (* l = x' :: l' *)
simpl. intros [H | H].
+ rewrite H. left. reflexivity.
+ right. apply IHl'. apply H.
Qed.
intros A B f l x.
induction l as [|x' l' IHl'].
- (* l = nil, contradiction *)
simpl. intros [].
- (* l = x' :: l' *)
simpl. intros [H | H].
+ rewrite H. left. reflexivity.
+ right. apply IHl'. apply H.
Qed.
Applying Theorems to Arguments
Check plus_comm : ∀ n m : nat, n + m = m + n.
Coq checks the statement of the plus_comm theorem (or prints
it for us, if we leave off the part beginning with the colon) in
the same way that it checks the type of any term that we ask it
to Check.
Why?
Similarly, the statement of a theorem tells us what we can use
that theorem for.
This is often handy in proof scripts -- e.g., suppose we want too
prove the following:
The reason is that the identifier plus_comm actually refers to a proof object, which represents a logical derivation establishing of the truth of the statement ∀ n m : nat, n + m = m + n. The type of this object is the proposition which it is a proof of.
The type of a "computational" object tells us what we can do with that object.
- e.g., if we have a term of type nat → nat → nat, we can give it two nats as arguments and get a nat back.
- if we have an object of type n = m → n + n = m + m and we provide it an "argument" of type n = m, we can derive n + n = m + m.
Coq actually allows us to apply a theorem as if it were a function.
Lemma plus_comm3 :
∀ x y z, x + (y + z) = (z + y) + x.
It appears at first sight that we ought to be able to prove this
by rewriting with plus_comm twice to make the two sides match.
The problem, however, is that the second rewrite will undo the
effect of the first.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
We can fix this by applying plus_comm to the arguments we want it be to instantiated with. Then the rewrite can only happen in one place.
Lemma plus_comm3_take3 :
∀ x y z, x + (y + z) = (z + y) + x.
Proof.
intros x y z.
rewrite plus_comm.
rewrite (plus_comm y z).
reflexivity.
Qed.
Let's see another example of using a theorem like a function.
Theorem in_not_nil :
∀ A (x : A) (l : list A), In x l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros A x l H. unfold not. intro Hl.
rewrite Hl in H.
simpl in H.
apply H.
Qed.
We should be able to use this theorem to prove the special case
where x is 42. However, naively, the tactic apply in_not_nil
will fail because it cannot infer the value of x.
Lemma in_not_nil_42 :
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
Fail apply in_not_nil.
Abort.
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take2 :
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil with (x := 42).
apply H.
Qed.
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil with (x := 42).
apply H.
Qed.
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take3 :
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil in H.
apply H.
Qed.
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil in H.
apply H.
Qed.
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take4 :
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil nat 42).
apply H.
Qed.
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil nat 42).
apply H.
Qed.
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take5 :
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil _ _ _ H).
Qed.
∀ l : list nat, In 42 l → l ≠ [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil _ _ _ H).
Qed.
Suppose we have
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
What is the type of this proof object?
trans_eq nat a b 42 H1 H2
(1) a = b
(2) 42 = a
(3) a = 42
(4) Does not typecheck
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
trans_eq nat a b 42 H1 H2
Check trans_eq nat a b 42 H1 H2
: a = 42.
: a = 42.
Suppose we have
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
What is the type of this proof object?
trans_eq nat b 42 a H2
(1) b = a
(2) b = a → 42 = a
(3) 42 = a → b = a
(4) Does not typecheck
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
trans_eq nat b 42 a H2
Check trans_eq nat b 42 a H2
: 42 = a → b = a.
: 42 = a → b = a.
Suppose we have
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
What is the type of this proof object?
trans_eq _ 42 a b
(1) a = b → b = 42 → a = 42
(2) 42 = a → a = b → 42 = b
(3) a = 42 → 42 = b → a = b
(4) Does not typecheck
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
trans_eq _ 42 a b
Check trans_eq _ 42 a b
: 42 = a → a = b → 42 = b.
: 42 = a → a = b → 42 = b.
Suppose we have
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
What is the type of this proof object?
trans_eq _ _ _ _ H2 H1
(1) b = a
(2) 42 = a
(3) a = 42
(4) Does not typecheck
a, b : nat
H1 : a = b
H2 : b = 42
trans_eq : ∀ (X : Type) (n m o : X),
n = m → m = o → n = o
trans_eq _ _ _ _ H2 H1
Fail Check trans_eq _ _ _ _ H2 H1.
Coq vs. Set Theory
Functional Extensionality
Example function_equality_ex1 :
(fun x ⇒ 3 + x) = (fun x ⇒ (pred 4) + x).
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
In common mathematical practice, two functions f and g are
considered equal if they produce the same output on every input:
(∀ x, f x = g x) → f = g
This is known as the principle of functional extensionality.
(∀ x, f x = g x) → f = g
However, functional extensionality is not part of Coq's built-in logic. This means that some apparently "obvious" propositions are not provable.
Example function_equality_ex2 :
(fun x ⇒ plus x 1) = (fun x ⇒ plus 1 x).
Proof.
(* Stuck *)
Abort.
Axiom functional_extensionality : ∀ {X Y: Type}
{f g : X → Y},
(∀ (x:X), f x = g x) → f = g.
Defining something as an Axiom has the same effect as stating a
theorem and skipping its proof using Admitted, but it alerts the
reader that this isn't just something we're going to come back and
fill in later!
We can now invoke functional extensionality in proofs:
Example function_equality_ex2 :
(fun x ⇒ plus x 1) = (fun x ⇒ plus 1 x).
Proof.
apply functional_extensionality. intros x.
apply plus_comm.
Qed.
Naturally, we must be careful when adding new axioms into Coq's logic, as this can render it inconsistent -- that is, it may become possible to prove every proposition, including False, 2+2=5, etc.!
To check whether a particular proof relies on any additional axioms, use the Print Assumptions command.
Print Assumptions function_equality_ex2.
(* ===>
Axioms:
functional_extensionality :
forall (X Y : Type) (f g : X -> Y),
(forall x : X, f x = g x) -> f = g *)
Is this provable by reflexivity, i.e., without
functional_extensionality?
(fun xs ⇒ 1 :: xs) = (fun xs ⇒ [1] ++ xs)
(1) Yes
(2) No
Example cons_1_eq_ex : (fun xs ⇒ 1 :: xs) = (fun xs ⇒ [1] ++ xs).
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Propositions vs. Booleans
Example even_42_bool : evenb 42 = true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
... or that there exists some k such that n = double k.
Example even_42_prop : even 42.
Proof. unfold even. ∃ 21. reflexivity. Qed.
Of course, it would be pretty strange if these two
characterizations of evenness did not describe the same set of
natural numbers! Fortunately, we can prove that they do...
Theorem even_bool_prop : ∀ n,
evenb n = true ↔ even n.
evenb n = true ↔ even n.
Proof.
intros n. split.
- intros H. destruct (evenb_double_conv n) as [k Hk].
rewrite Hk. rewrite H. ∃ k. reflexivity.
- intros [k Hk]. rewrite Hk. apply evenb_double.
Qed.
intros n. split.
- intros H. destruct (evenb_double_conv n) as [k Hk].
rewrite Hk. rewrite H. ∃ k. reflexivity.
- intros [k Hk]. rewrite Hk. apply evenb_double.
Qed.
In view of this theorem, we say that the boolean computation
evenb n is reflected in the truth of the proposition
∃ k, n = double k.
Similarly, to state that two numbers n and m are equal, we can say either
- (1) that n =? m returns true, or
- (2) that n = m.
Theorem eqb_eq : ∀ n1 n2 : nat,
n1 =? n2 = true ↔ n1 = n2.
Proof.
intros n1 n2. split.
- apply eqb_true.
- intros H. rewrite H. rewrite <- eqb_refl. reflexivity.
Qed.
intros n1 n2. split.
- apply eqb_true.
- intros H. rewrite H. rewrite <- eqb_refl. reflexivity.
Qed.
However, even when the boolean and propositional formulations of a claim are equivalent from a purely logical perspective, they are often not equivalent from the point of view of convenience for some specific purpose.
For these examples, the propositional claims are more useful than their boolean counterparts, but this is not always the case. For instance, we cannot test whether a general proposition is true or not in a function definition; as a consequence, the following code fragment is rejected:
Fail
Definition is_even_prime n :=
if n = 2 then true
else false.
An important side benefit of stating facts using booleans is enabling some proof automation through computation with Coq terms, a technique known as proof by reflection.
Example even_1000 : even 1000.
The most direct way to prove this is to give the value of k
explicitly.
Proof. unfold even. ∃ 500. reflexivity. Qed.
The proof of the corresponding boolean statement is even
simpler (because we don't have to invent the witness: Coq's
computation mechanism does it for us!).
Example even_1000' : evenb 1000 = true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
What is interesting is that, since the two notions are equivalent, we can use the boolean formulation to prove the other one without mentioning the value 500 explicitly:
Example even_1000'' : even 1000.
Proof. apply even_bool_prop. reflexivity. Qed.
Example not_even_1001 : evenb 1001 = false.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
In contrast, propositional negation can be more difficult
to work with directly.
Example not_even_1001' : ~(even 1001).
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
Lemma plus_eqb_example : ∀ n m p : nat,
n =? m = true → n + p =? m + p = true.
Proof.
(* WORK IN CLASS *) Admitted.
We won't discuss reflection any further here, but it serves as a
good example showing the complementary strengths of booleans and
general propositions, and being able to cross back and forth
between the boolean and propositional worlds will often be
convenient in later chapters.
The following reasoning principle is not derivable in
Coq (though, again, it can consistently be added):
Classical vs. Constructive Logic
Definition excluded_middle := ∀ P : Prop,
P ∨ ¬P.
Logics like Coq's, which do not assume the excluded middle, are
referred to as constructive logics.
More conventional logical systems such as ZFC, in which the
excluded middle does hold for arbitrary propositions, are referred
to as classical.