SubSubtyping

A Motivating Example

Suppose we are writing a program involving two record types defined as follows:
      Person  = {name:String, age:Nat}
      Student = {name:String, age:Nat, gpa:Nat}
Problem: In the pure STLC with records, the following term is not typable:
    (\r:Person. (r.age)+1) {name="Pat",age=21,gpa=1}
This is a shame.

Idea: Introduce subtyping, formalizing the observation that "some types are better than others."
Safe substitution principle:
  • S is a subtype of T, written S <: T, if a value of type S can safely be used in any context where a value of type T is expected.

Subtyping and Object-Oriented Languages

Subtyping plays a fundamental role in OO programming languages.
Roughly, an object can be thought of as a record of functions ("methods") and data values ("fields" or "instance variables").
  • Invoking a method m of an object o on some arguments a1..an consists of projecting out the m field of o and applying it to a1..an.
The type of an object is a class (or an interface).
Classes are related by the subclass relation.
  • An object belonging to a subclass must provide all the methods and fields of one belonging to a superclass, plus possibly some more.
  • Thus a subclass object can be used anywhere a superclass object is expected.
  • Very handy for organizing large libraries

Of course, real OO languages have lots of other features...
  • mutable fields
  • "private" and other visibility modifiers
  • method inheritance
  • static components
  • etc., etc.
We'll ignore all these and focus on core mechanisms.

The Subsumption Rule

Our goal for this chapter is to add subtyping to the simply typed lambda-calculus (with some of the basic extensions from MoreStlc). This involves two steps:
  • Defining a binary subtype relation between types.
  • Enriching the typing relation to take subtyping into account.
The second step is actually very simple. We add just a single rule to the typing relation: the so-called rule of subsumption:
Gamma ⊢ t1 ∈ T1     T1 <: T2 (T_Sub)  

Gamma ⊢ t1 ∈ T2
This rule says, intuitively, that it is OK to "forget" some of what we know about a term.

The Subtype Relation

The first step -- the definition of the relation S <: T -- is where all the action is. Let's look at each of the clauses of its definition.

Structural Rules

To start off, we impose two "structural rules" that are independent of any particular type constructor: a rule of transitivity, which says intuitively that, if S is better (richer, safer) than U and U is better than T, then S is better than T...
S <: U    U <: T (S_Trans)  

S <: T
... and a rule of reflexivity, since certainly any type T is as good as itself:
   (S_Refl)  

T <: T

Products

Now we consider the individual type constructors, one by one, beginning with product types. We consider one pair to be a subtype of another if each of its components is.
S1 <: T1    S2 <: T2 (S_Prod)  

S1 * S2 <: T1 * T2

Arrows

Suppose we have functions f and g with these types:
       f : CStudent
       g : (CPerson) → D
Is it safe to allow the application g f?
Yes.
So we want:
      CStudent <: CPerson I.e., arrow is covariant in its right-hand argument.

Now suppose we have:
       f : PersonC
       g : (StudentC) → D
Is it safe to allow the application g f?
Again yes.
So we want:
      PersonC <: StudentC I.e., arrow is contravariant in its left-hand argument.

Putting these together...
T1 <: S1    S2 <: T2 (S_Arrow)  

S1 -> S2 <: T1 -> T2
Suppose we have S <: T and U <: V. Which of the following subtyping assertions is false?
(1) S×U <: T×V
(2) TU <: SU
(3) (SU) (S×V) <: (SU) (T×U)
(4) (T×U) V <: (S×U) V
(5) SU <: SV
Suppose again that we have S <: T and U <: V. Which of the following is incorrect?
(1) (TT)*U <: (ST)*V
(2) TU <: SV
(3) (SU) (SV) <: (TU) (TV)
(4) (SV) V <: (TU) V
(5) S (VU) <: S (UU)

Records

What about subtyping for record types?

The basic intuition is that it is always safe to use a "bigger" record in place of a "smaller" one. That is, given a record type, adding extra fields will always result in a subtype. If some code is expecting a record with fields x and y, it is perfectly safe for it to receive a record with fields x, y, and z; the z field will simply be ignored. For example,
    {name:String, age:Nat, gpa:Nat} <: {name:String, age:Nat}
    {name:String, age:Nat} <: {name:String}
    {name:String} <: {}
This is known as "width subtyping" for records.

We can also create a subtype of a record type by replacing the type of one of its fields with a subtype. If some code is expecting a record with a field x of type T, it will be happy with a record having a field x of type S as long as S is a subtype of T. For example,
    {x:Student} <: {x:Person} This is known as "depth subtyping".

Finally, although the fields of a record type are written in a particular order, the order does not really matter. For example,
    {name:String,age:Nat} <: {age:Nat,name:String} This is known as "permutation subtyping".

We could formalize these requirements in a single subtyping rule for records as follows:
forall jk in j1..jn,
exists ip in i1..im, such that
jk=ip and Sp <: Tk (S_Rcd)  

{i1:S1...im:Sm} <: {j1:T1...jn:Tn}
That is, the record on the left should have all the field labels of the one on the right (and possibly more), while the types of the common fields should be in the subtype relation.
However, this rule is rather heavy and hard to read, so it is often decomposed into three simpler rules, which can be combined using S_Trans to achieve all the same effects.

First, adding fields to the end of a record type gives a subtype:
n > m (S_RcdWidth)  

{i1:T1...in:Tn} <: {i1:T1...im:Tm}
We can use S_RcdWidth to drop later fields of a multi-field record while keeping earlier fields, showing for example that {age:Nat,name:String} <: {age:Nat}.

Second, subtyping can be applied inside the components of a compound record type:
S1 <: T1 ... Sn <: Tn (S_RcdDepth)  

{i1:S1...in:Sn} <: {i1:T1...in:Tn}
For example, we can use S_RcdDepth and S_RcdWidth together to show that {y:Student, x:Nat} <: {y:Person}.

Third, subtyping can reorder fields. For example, we want {name:String, gpa:Nat, age:Nat} <: Person, but we haven't quite achieved this yet: using just S_RcdDepth and S_RcdWidth we can only drop fields from the end of a record type. So we add:
{i1:S1...in:Sn} is a permutation of {j1:T1...jn:Tn} (S_RcdPerm)  

{i1:S1...in:Sn} <: {j1:T1...jn:Tn}

It is worth noting that full-blown language designs may choose not to adopt all of these subtyping rules. For example, in Java:
  • Each class member (field or method) can be assigned a single index, adding new indices "on the right" as more members are added in subclasses (i.e., no permutation for classes).
  • A class may implement multiple interfaces -- so-called "multiple inheritance" of interfaces (i.e., permutation is allowed for interfaces).
  • In early versions of Java, a subclass could not change the argument or result types of a method of its superclass (i.e., no depth subtyping or no arrow subtyping, depending how you look at it).

Top

Finally, it is convenient to give the subtype relation a maximum element -- a type that lies above every other type and is inhabited by all (well-typed) values. We do this by adding to the language one new type constant, called Top, together with a subtyping rule that places it above every other type in the subtype relation:
   (S_Top)  

S <: Top
The Top type is an analog of the Object type in Java and C#.

Summary

In summary, we form the STLC with subtyping by starting with the pure STLC (over some set of base types) and then...
  • adding a base type Top,
  • adding the rule of subsumption
    Gamma ⊢ t1 ∈ T1     T1 <: T2 (T_Sub)  

    Gamma ⊢ t1 ∈ T2
    to the typing relation, and
  • defining a subtype relation as follows:
    S <: U    U <: T (S_Trans)  

    S <: T
       (S_Refl)  

    T <: T
       (S_Top)  

    S <: Top
    S1 <: T1    S2 <: T2 (S_Prod)  

    S1 * S2 <: T1 * T2
    T1 <: S1    S2 <: T2 (S_Arrow)  

    S1 -> S2 <: T1 -> T2
    n > m (S_RcdWidth)  

    {i1:T1...in:Tn} <: {i1:T1...im:Tm}
    S1 <: T1 ... Sn <: Tn (S_RcdDepth)  

    {i1:S1...in:Sn} <: {i1:T1...in:Tn}
    {i1:S1...in:Sn} is a permutation of {j1:T1...jn:Tn} (S_RcdPerm)  

    {i1:S1...in:Sn} <: {j1:T1...jn:Tn}
Suppose we have S <: T and U <: V. Which of the following subtyping assertions is false?
(1) S×U <: Top
(2) {i1:S,i2:T}->U <: {i1:S,i2:T,i3:V}->U
(3) (ST) (Top Top) <: (ST) Top
(4) (Top Top) V <: Top V
(5) S {i1:U,i2:V} <: S {i2:V,i1:U}
How about these?
(1) {i1:Top} <: Top
(2) Top (Top Top) <: Top Top
(3) {i1:T} {i1:T} <: {i1:T,i2:S} Top
(4) {i1:T,i2:V,i3:V} <: {i1:S,i2:U} × {i3:V}
(5) Top {i1:U,i2:V} <: {i1:S} {i2:V,i1:V}
What is the smallest type T that makes the following assertion true?
       a:A ⊢ (\p:(A×T). (p.snd) (p.fst)) (a, \z:A.z) \in A
(1) Top
(2) A
(3) TopTop
(4) TopA
(5) AA
(6) ATop
What is the largest type T that makes the following assertion true?
       a:A ⊢ (\p:(A×T). (p.snd) (p.fst)) (a, \z:A.z) \in A
(1) Top
(2) A
(3) TopTop
(4) TopA
(5) AA
(6) ATop
"The type Bool has no proper subtypes." (I.e., the only type smaller than Bool is Bool itself.)
(1) True
(2) False
"Suppose S, T1, and T2 are types with S <: T1 T2. Then S itself is an arrow type -- i.e., S = S1 S2 for some S1 and S2 -- with T1 <: S1 and S2 <: T2."
(1) True
(2) False

Formal Definitions

Most of the definitions needed to formalize what we've discussed above -- in particular, the syntax and operational semantics of the language -- are identical to what we saw in the last chapter. We just need to extend the typing relation with the subsumption rule and add a new Inductive definition for the subtyping relation. Let's first do the identical bits.

Syntax

(Omitting records, to avoid dealing with ... stuff.)
Inductive ty : Type :=
  | Ty_Top : ty
  | Ty_Bool : ty
  | Ty_Base : stringty
  | Ty_Arrow : tytyty
  | Ty_Unit : ty
.

Inductive tm : Type :=
  | tm_var : stringtm
  | tm_app : tmtmtm
  | tm_abs : stringtytmtm
  | tm_true : tm
  | tm_false : tm
  | tm_if : tmtmtmtm
  | tm_unit : tm
.

Substitution

The definition of substitution remains exactly the same as for the pure STLC.

Fixpoint subst (x : string) (s : tm) (t : tm) : tm :=
  match t with
  | tm_var y
      if eqb_string x y then s else t
  | <{\y:T, t1}> ⇒
      if eqb_string x y then t else <{\y:T, [x:=s] t1}>
  | <{t1 t2}> ⇒
      <{([x:=s] t1) ([x:=s] t2)}>
  | <{true}> ⇒
      <{true}>
  | <{false}> ⇒
      <{false}>
  | <{if t1 then t2 else t3}> ⇒
      <{if ([x:=s] t1) then ([x:=s] t2) else ([x:=s] t3)}>
  | <{unit}> ⇒
      <{unit}>
  end
where "'[' x ':=' s ']' t" := (subst x s t) (in custom stlc).

Reduction

Likewise the definitions of value and step.
Inductive value : tmProp :=
  | v_abs : x T2 t1,
      value <{\x:T2, t1}>
  | v_true :
      value <{true}>
  | v_false :
      value <{false}>
  | v_unit :
      value <{unit}>
.


Inductive step : tmtmProp :=
  | ST_AppAbs : x T2 t1 v2,
         value v2
         <{(\x:T2, t1) v2}> --> <{ [x:=v2]t1 }>
  | ST_App1 : t1 t1' t2,
         t1 --> t1'
         <{t1 t2}> --> <{t1' t2}>
  | ST_App2 : v1 t2 t2',
         value v1
         t2 --> t2'
         <{v1 t2}> --> <{v1 t2'}>
  | ST_IfTrue : t1 t2,
      <{if true then t1 else t2}> --> t1
  | ST_IfFalse : t1 t2,
      <{if false then t1 else t2}> --> t2
  | ST_If : t1 t1' t2 t3,
      t1 --> t1'
      <{if t1 then t2 else t3}> --> <{if t1' then t2 else t3}>
where "t '-->' t'" := (step t t').

Subtyping

The definition of subtyping is just what we sketched in the motivating discussion.

Inductive subtype : tytyProp :=
  | S_Refl : T,
      T <: T
  | S_Trans : S U T,
      S <: U
      U <: T
      S <: T
  | S_Top : S,
      S <: <{Top}>
  | S_Arrow : S1 S2 T1 T2,
      T1 <: S1
      S2 <: T2
      <{S1S2}> <: <{T1T2}>
where "T '<:' U" := (subtype T U).
Note that we don't need any special rules for base types (Bool and Base): they are automatically subtypes of themselves (by S_Refl) and Top (by S_Top), and that's all we want.

Typing

The only change to the typing relation is the addition of the rule of subsumption, T_Sub.
Inductive has_type : contexttmtyProp :=
  (* Same as before: *)
  (* pure STLC *)
  | T_Var : Gamma x T1,
      Gamma x = Some T1
      Gammax \in T1
  | T_Abs : Gamma x T1 T2 t1,
      (x > T2 ; Gamma) ⊢ t1 \in T1
      Gamma ⊢ \x:T2, t1 \in (T2T1)
  | T_App : T1 T2 Gamma t1 t2,
      Gammat1 \in (T2T1) →
      Gammat2 \in T2
      Gammat1 t2 \in T1
  | T_True : Gamma,
       Gammatrue \in Bool
  | T_False : Gamma,
       Gammafalse \in Bool
  | T_If : t1 t2 t3 T1 Gamma,
       Gammat1 \in Bool
       Gammat2 \in T1
       Gammat3 \in T1
       Gammaif t1 then t2 else t3 \in T1
  | T_Unit : Gamma,
      Gammaunit \in Unit
  (* New rule of subsumption: *)
  | T_Sub : Gamma t1 T1 T2,
      Gammat1 \in T1
      T1 <: T2
      Gammat1 \in T2

where "Gamma '⊢' t '∈' T" := (has_type Gamma t T).

Properties

We want the same properties as always: progress + preservation.
  • Statements of these theorems don't need to change, compared to pure STLC
  • But proofs are a bit more involved, to account for the additional flexibility in the typing relation

Inversion Lemmas for Subtyping

Before we look at the properties of the typing relation, we need to establish a couple of critical structural properties of the subtype relation:
  • Bool is the only subtype of Bool, and
  • every subtype of an arrow type is itself an arrow type.
Formally:
Lemma sub_inversion_Bool : U,
     U <: <{Bool}> →
     U = <{Bool}>.
Proof with auto.
  intros U Hs.
  remember <{Bool}> as V.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Lemma sub_inversion_arrow : U V1 V2,
     U <: <{V1V2}> →
      U1 U2,
     U = <{U1U2}> ∧ V1 <: U1U2 <: V2.
Proof with eauto.
  intros U V1 V2 Hs.
  remember <{V1V2}> as V.
  generalize dependent V2. generalize dependent V1.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Canonical Forms

The proof of progress uses facts of the form "every value belonging to an arrow type is an abstraction."
In the pure STLC, such facts are "immediate from the definition" (formally, we can use the inversion tactic).
With subtyping, they require real (inductive) proofs...
Lemma canonical_forms_of_arrow_types : Gamma s T1 T2,
  Gammas \in (T1T2) →
  value s
   x S1 s2,
     s = <{\x:S1,s2}>.
Proof with eauto.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Similarly, the canonical forms of type Bool are the constants tm_true and tm_false.
Lemma canonical_forms_of_Bool : Gamma s,
  Gammas \in Bool
  value s
  s = tm_trues = tm_false.
Proof with eauto.
  intros Gamma s Hty Hv.
  remember <{Bool}> as T.
  induction Hty; try solve_by_invert...
  - (* T_Sub *)
    subst. apply sub_inversion_Bool in H. subst...
Qed.

Progress

Theorem (Progress): For any term t and type T, if empty t \in T then t is a value or t --> t' for some term t'.
Proof: Let t and T be given, with empty t \in T. Proceed by induction on the typing derivation.
The cases for T_Abs, T_Unit, T_True and T_False are immediate because abstractions, tm_unit, tm_true, and tm_false are already values. The T_Var case is vacuous because variables cannot be typed in the empty context. The remaining cases are more interesting:
  • If the last step in the typing derivation uses rule T_App, then there are terms t1 t2 and types T1 and T2 such that t = t1 t2, T = T2, empty t1 \in T1 T2, and empty t2 \in T1. Moreover, by the induction hypothesis, either t1 is a value or it steps, and either t2 is a value or it steps. There are three possibilities to consider:
    • Suppose t1 --> t1' for some term t1'. Then t1 t2 --> t1' t2 by ST_App1.
    • Suppose t1 is a value and t2 --> t2' for some term t2'. Then t1 t2 --> t1 t2' by rule ST_App2 because t1 is a value.
    • Finally, suppose t1 and t2 are both values. By the canonical forms lemma for arrow types, we know that t1 has the form \x:S1.s2 for some x, S1, and s2. But then (\x:S1.s2) t2 --> [x:=t2]s2 by ST_AppAbs, since t2 is a value.
  • If the final step of the derivation uses rule T_Test, then there are terms t1, t2, and t3 such that t = tm_if t1 then t2 else t3, with empty t1 \in Bool and with empty t2 \in T and empty t3 \in T. Moreover, by the induction hypothesis, either t1 is a value or it steps.
    • If t1 is a value, then by the canonical forms lemma for booleans, either t1 = tm_true or t1 = tm_false. In either case, t can step, using rule ST_TestTrue or ST_TestFalse.
    • If t1 can step, then so can t, by rule ST_Test.
  • If the final step of the derivation is by T_Sub, then there is a type T2 such that T1 <: T2 and empty t1 \in T1. The desired result is exactly the induction hypothesis for the typing subderivation.
Formally:
Theorem progress : t T,
     emptyt \in T
     value t t', t --> t'.
Proof with eauto.
  intros t T Ht.
  remember empty as Gamma.
  induction Ht; subst Gamma; auto.
  - (* T_Var *)
    discriminate.
  - (* T_App *)
    right.
    destruct IHHt1; subst...
    + (* t1 is a value *)
      destruct IHHt2; subst...
      × (* t2 is a value *)
        eapply canonical_forms_of_arrow_types in Ht1; [|assumption].
        destruct Ht1 as [x [S1 [s2 H1]]]. subst.
         (<{ [x:=t2]s2 }>)...
      × (* t2 steps *)
        destruct H0 as [t2' Hstp]. <{ t1 t2' }>...
    + (* t1 steps *)
      destruct H as [t1' Hstp]. <{ t1' t2 }>...
  - (* T_Test *)
    right.
    destruct IHHt1.
    + (* t1 is a value *) eauto.
    + apply canonical_forms_of_Bool in Ht1; [|assumption].
      destruct Ht1; subst...
    + destruct H. rename x into t1'. eauto.
Qed.

Inversion Lemmas for Typing

We also need an inversion lemma for a structural fact about the typing relation that is "obvious from the definition" in pure STLC.
Lemma: If Gamma \x:S1.t2 \in T, then there is a type S2 such that x>S1; Gamma t2 \in S2 and S1 S2 <: T.
(Notice that the lemma does not say, "then T itself is an arrow type" -- this is tempting, but false!)
Proof: Let Gamma, x, S1, t2 and T be given as described. Proceed by induction on the derivation of Gamma \x:S1.t2 \in T. Cases T_Var, T_App, are vacuous as those rules cannot be used to give a type to a syntactic abstraction.
  • If the last step of the derivation is a use of T_Abs then there is a type T12 such that T = S1 T12 and x:S1; Gamma t2 \in T12. Picking T12 for S2 gives us what we need: S1 T12 <: S1 T12 follows from S_Refl.
  • If the last step of the derivation is a use of T_Sub then there is a type S such that S <: T and Gamma \x:S1.t2 \in S. The IH for the typing subderivation tells us that there is some type S2 with S1 S2 <: S and x:S1; Gamma t2 \in S2. Picking type S2 gives us what we need, since S1 S2 <: T then follows by S_Trans.

Formally:
Lemma typing_inversion_abs : Gamma x S1 t2 T,
     Gamma ⊢ \x:S1,t2 \in T
      S2,
       <{S1S2}> <: T
       ∧ (x > S1 ; Gamma) ⊢ t2 \in S2.
Proof with eauto.
  intros Gamma x S1 t2 T H.
  remember <{\x:S1,t2}> as t.
  induction H;
    inversion Heqt; subst; intros; try solve_by_invert.
  - (* T_Abs *)
     T1...
  - (* T_Sub *)
    destruct IHhas_type as [S2 [Hsub Hty]]...
  Qed.

Lemma typing_inversion_var : Gamma (x:string) T,
  Gammax \in T
   S,
    Gamma x = Some SS <: T.
Proof with eauto.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Lemma typing_inversion_app : Gamma t1 t2 T2,
  Gammat1 t2 \in T2
   T1,
    Gammat1 \in (T1T2) ∧
    Gammat2 \in T1.
Proof with eauto.
  (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Weakening

The weakening lemma is proved as in pure STLC.
Lemma weakening : Gamma Gamma' t T,
     inclusion Gamma Gamma'
     Gammat \in T
     Gamma't \in T.
Proof.
  intros Gamma Gamma' t T H Ht.
  generalize dependent Gamma'.
  induction Ht; eauto using inclusion_update.
Qed.

Lemma weakening_empty : Gamma t T,
     emptyt \in T
     Gammat \in T.
Proof.
  intros Gamma t T.
  eapply weakening.
  discriminate.
Qed.

Substitution

The substitution lemma is done as in pure STLC but using induction on the typing derivation rather than on terms.
Lemma substitution_preserves_typing : Gamma x U t v T,
   (x > U ; Gamma) ⊢ t \in T
   emptyv \in U
   Gamma ⊢ [x:=v]t \in T.
Proof.
Proof.
  intros Gamma x U t v T Ht Hv.
  remember (x > U; Gamma) as Gamma'.
  generalize dependent Gamma.
  induction Ht; intros Gamma' G; simpl; eauto.
 (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Preservation

The proof of preservation now proceeds pretty much as in earlier chapters, using the substitution lemma at the appropriate point and the inversion lemma from above to extract structural information from typing assumptions.
Theorem (Preservation): If t, t' are terms and T is a type such that empty t \in T and t --> t', then empty t' \in T.
Proof: Let t and T be given such that empty t \in T. We proceed by induction on the structure of this typing derivation, leaving t' general. The cases T_Abs, T_Unit, T_True, and T_False cases are vacuous because abstractions and constants don't step. Case T_Var is vacuous as well, since the context is empty.
  • If the final step of the derivation is by T_App, then there are terms t1 and t2 and types T1 and T2 such that t = t1 t2, T = T2, empty t1 \in T1 T2, and empty t2 \in T1.
    By the definition of the step relation, there are three ways t1 t2 can step. Cases ST_App1 and ST_App2 follow immediately by the induction hypotheses for the typing subderivations and a use of T_App.
    Suppose instead t1 t2 steps by ST_AppAbs. Then t1 = \x:S.t12 for some type S and term t12, and t' = [x:=t2]t12.
    By lemma abs_arrow, we have T1 <: S and x:S1 s2 \in T2. It then follows by the substitution lemma (substitution_preserves_typing) that empty [x:=t2] t12 \in T2 as desired.
    • If the final step of the derivation uses rule T_Test, then there are terms t1, t2, and t3 such that t = tm_if t1 then t2 else t3, with empty t1 \in Bool and with empty t2 \in T and empty t3 \in T. Moreover, by the induction hypothesis, if t1 steps to t1' then empty t1' : Bool. There are three cases to consider, depending on which rule was used to show t --> t'.
      • If t --> t' by rule ST_Test, then t' = tm_if t1' then t2 else t3 with t1 --> t1'. By the induction hypothesis, empty t1' \in Bool, and so empty t' \in T by T_Test.
      • If t --> t' by rule ST_TestTrue or ST_TestFalse, then either t' = t2 or t' = t3, and empty t' \in T follows by assumption.
  • If the final step of the derivation is by T_Sub, then there is a type S such that S <: T and empty t \in S. The result is immediate by the induction hypothesis for the typing subderivation and an application of T_Sub.
Theorem preservation : t t' T,
     emptyt \in T
     t --> t'
     emptyt' \in T.
Proof with eauto.
  intros t t' T HT. generalize dependent t'.
  remember empty as Gamma.
  induction HT;
       intros t' HE; subst;
       try solve [inversion HE; subst; eauto].
  - (* T_App *)
    inversion HE; subst...
    (* Most of the cases are immediate by induction,
       and eauto takes care of them *)

    + (* ST_AppAbs *)
      destruct (abs_arrow _ _ _ _ _ HT1) as [HA1 HA2].
      apply substitution_preserves_typing with T0...
Qed.